Is Socrates Guilty?
Why am I writing this? I’m about to embark on a course entitled
‘Plato and the Pre-Socratics’, and I figured I would familiarise myself with
some interpretive issues concerning Plato. I am relatively familiar with
his texts, but have never ventured into the wilderness that is Plato
interpretation. It isn’t my fear of the interpreters that has stopped me
from going further, it is simply the need I felt to first read the texts
carefully and then see what other people have to say. Now that I am ready to
hear what other people have to say, I have gone through the first three essays
of The Trial and Execution of
Socrates: Sources and Controversies entitled: The Impiety of Socrates (M.F. Burnyeat), The Trial of Socrates: And a
Religious Crisis (Robert
Parker), and Does Piety Pay?
Socrates on Prayer and Sacrifice (Mark
L. McPherran). I have also read the first part of Karl Popper’s The Open Society and Its Enemies. The idea here is to read essays,
not necessarily linearly, as the insights found in one text may lead me to
previous essays, and then provide some sort of analysis with a narrative. So
here it goes.
In The
Impiety of Socrates, M.F. Burnyeat provides a new 'reading' strategy
one could use to read the Apology.
Why would one propose a new strategy to reading Plato? According to
Burnyeat, much of Plato scholarship is ‘inconclusive guess work. Readers have
often asked: ‘What is the relation between the historical Socrates and the
Socrates portrayed in Plato’s Apology?’
Burnyeat admits early that he has nothing to add to this enterprise, and
instead submits another potential way to read the
Apology. The Apology should be read as ‘personal
challenge’. What does he mean by this? As the Socrates of the Apology could not be identical to the real
Socrates, the jury could also be not identical with the real jury. Therefore, a
reader of the Apology ‘whether in ancient times or
(here) today’, is asked to ‘pass judgment on Socrates’. Plato, Burnyeat claims,
penned the Apology in a forensic form; unlike the
routine dialogue where one is invited to 'join in a philosophical
discussion', this dialogue takes the shape of a legal text. Burnyeat cites an
'ancient rhetorician' who also noted this seemingly legal style. This rhetorician
saw the Apology as consisting in three main
themes. First, the two drives of defence and accusation are interconnected to
the form the judicial theme. Secondly, the work has a theme of praise for the
character of Socrates. The third theme is the normative undercurrent of the
work that asks: 'what is a philosopher?' The drive of accusation is, Burnyeat
claims, the strongest aspect of the work, insofar as it is an
accusation levelled against Greek culture and religion and has much to do
with the question of whether he would be thought of as guilty or not by an
Athenian juror.
However, one is
not supposed to judge as themselves; Burnyeat asks that you assume the position
of an Athenian juror and think of what the most rational thing for you to have
thought given your knowledge of Socrates. Therefore, there seems to be a degree
of imagination involved in what Burnyeat prescribes. But without digressing
into a premature critique of Burnyeat's interpretive method, let me state
the charges as they are presented by Socrates himself at 24C of the Apology. Here
are the charges: 1.not believing in the Gods of the State, 2. introducing new
divinities, and 3.corrupting the youth. I’ll begin with the first charge;
does Burnyeat think Socrates guilty of not believing in the Gods of the
state? Burnyeat's first point once this question is raised is that, given
his interpretive strategy, insofar as Socrates never says in the Apology that he believes in the gods of
the state, why should we think he is innocent? In any legal case, if someone is
attempting to prove his innocence, one will surely argue against his/her
participation the illegal activity. Why then would Socrates completely ignore
this rhetorical strategy?
Given that
Socrates doesn't defend himself of this charge, what would a reasonable
Athenian juror conclude based on his knowledge of Socrates? Burnyeat
argues that Socrates would be perceived as a threat to Athenian culture and its
religion. The god Socrates speaks of is radically different than Athenian
gods, so much so in fact that the ideal Athenian juror (like you) would
consider Socrates guilty of the first charge. The god of the 'Socratic
religion' is a god that demands virtue and constant questioning from human
beings (as they truly do not have virtue); unlike the gods of Athens, which
teach clear ideas of what virtue is, and claim that you need gods to achieve
it. For instance, the gods of Greek religion are gods one could barter with to
get what you wanted in tough situations, yet the Socratic god can only do as
virtue dictates and grants special treatment to no one. The patent hubris
involved in claiming humans do not need help from the gods would, Burnyeat
argues, undoubtedly raise fear in an Athenian juror
of repercussions from the gods in relation to Socrates' impiety. I
would argue that, insofar as Socrates is perceived as an educator, and is seen
as teaching things that undermine Athenian culture and religion, he would also
be thought guilty of corrupting the youth. It would be natural to think these
teaching would corrupt youth, as they teach one seemingly false things about
the gods and ethics; false things that will lead to a lack of eudaimonia for the individual and society.
Burnyeat's final
discussion centres on the precise differences between the Socratic god and the
Athenian gods. He approaches this topic by also proposing we read the Euthyphro
as a double question: a) ‘does Euthyphro act piously in charging his own father
with murder?’ and b) ‘is Socrates guilty of impiety?’ These two
questions can be thought of as one question, and this question is in the work:
'what is the nature of piety in relation to murder and to other things?'
Euthyphro's answer is famously that 'piety is what is pleasing to the gods'.
Burnyeat argues that, while this definition is the standard Greek definition of
piety, it is also revelatory as to a major problem within the Greek religion;
namely that it isn't always easy to know what will be pleasing to the gods. In
fact, Socrates' objection to this definition hovers around the fact that what
could be pious to one god could not be pious to another, as they differ as to
what pleases them. This directly affects Euthyphro, as he claims to think he is
pious for bringing his father to 'justice', as well as the dominant Greek
tradition who feels like it is pious. Socrates proposes a modification of
Euthyphro's principle, and manages to get Euthyphro to agree to it; 'something
is pious if it is loved by all the gods'. Burnyeat claims that, if this
principle had replaced the common principle of that day, the Athenian religion
would have been in peril. The god of Socrates would have never started the
Trojan war, or have caused the horrors of the Iliad or the Theogony.
Socrates' Gods
would have seemed different to the Athenian juror not only because of the
ethical deviance, but also because of the new powers this god possessed.
While not only speaking of a daemon,
Socrates also announces that, whatever the court decides, he will
remain unaffected; whether the charge is death or not. The
one thing the Greeks did not have that the gods did have was immortality. Is
Socrates stealing fire from the gods?
Burnyeat finds
Socrates guilty. However, he doesn't do so without bringing Plato down with
him. According to Burnyeat, Plato also believed Socrates was guilty. However,
as is made clear through the 'accusation' drive that Plato includes in the Apology, Plato was critical not of
Socrates, but of the people that found him guilty. For the Athenian people to
find Socrates guilty of impiety when he ultimately possessed the
secret of virtue, meant to Plato that Athens had failed at its mandate.
What do you think?
No comments:
Post a Comment