Can Batman Really Know what it is like to be a Bat?
In ‘What is it
like to be a Bat?’, Thomas Nagel argues that any attempt to reduce the mind to
a physical description will ultimately fail because: a) consciousness remains a
mystery and is a feature of the mind, b) the subjective qualitative experience
of consciousness is only available to those who experience it; all the
concepts/words one could use to describe someone else’s subjective qualitative
experience would be derivative from their own experience (therefore not giving
a good representation of the phenomenological aspects of the experience one is
trying to describe), and c) that while reducing other phenomena (light, water,
fire etc) gets one closer to objectivity, reducing the mind does the
opposite. This essay will outline Nagel’s
argument for the irreducibility of the mind, while also unpacking the larger
themes which call the meaning of any reductionist account into question.
The
first argument Nagel presents is an a
priori argument concerning the nature of reduction. Reduction is the process in which one takes a
phenomenon and reduces it to the components that bring about that phenomenon.
If one were to reduce the phenomenon of water for instance, one would analyse
all of the components of which water is composed and define water by the
relations amongst those simpler elements.
This article is essentially Nagel’s attempt at criticizing the
application of this method to consciousness.
Reduction (arguably) works with water because all aspects of water (H2O)
are known and reducible. However,
insofar as the mind has one aspect which is a relative unknown, any attempt at
reducing it will be incomplete; a system is reducible if and only if all
aspects of it are known and reducible. The notion of reducibility fails a
priori if consciousness is irreducible.
But
why is the mind inherently irreducible?
According to Nagel, there is an experience unique to every conscious
being; a feeling of what it is like for that thing to be that thing. Drawing on the nature of the experience of a
bat, Nagel attempts to show that ‘(w)ithout some idea, therefore, of what the
subjective character of a bats experience is, we cannot know what is required
of a physicalist theory (pg. 437).’ The idea is that, in order to reduce
something to its parts, one must possess an idea of what it is that needs to be
reduced. Because a key aspect of a bats
experience remains a mystery, namely what it is like to be that thing, any
attempt at reduction will lack a fundamental feature of the subject which is
willed to be reduced. This example is
meant to show that reductionist account will inevitably leave out a key feature
of mind.
The
subjective qualitative experience of what it is like for a bat, or what Nagel
calls the ‘phenomenological features’ (pg.437), is something only the bat holds
epistemic dominion over. If one were to
attempt an understanding at what it is like to be a bat for instance, one might
imagine what it is like to perceive the world through sonar, or to have wings
and eat insects. However, any mental
construction one could create as an attempt to understand the subjective
experience of what it is like to be a bat would be composed of bits of
experience gathered from memory, and therefore would only be an attempt at
describing an unknown experience in terms one was more familiar with. For instance, if one states that a bat is
using sonar to guide itself, one has no basis for making an informed claim about
what it is like for the bat to guide itself through the world using sonar, so
one uses his/her own imagination as an attempt to understand said
experience. This illustrates the issue
with reducing consciousness, as it will always drive one to attempt an
understanding of the phenomenological features of a system completely foreign
to it, leaving one with the inherently inadequate tools of imagination and
intuition.
This
does not mean we cannot say anything objective about the mind of a bat however.
We could say that bats experience fear, pain and hunger. However, we would: a) always be limited to
our understanding of what those are based on our experience, and b) we would
not be describing something about their subjective experience of what it is
like for a bat to experience these states subjectively. This reasoning can even apply between human
beings. For, I could never understand,
as Nagel points out, what the experience of someone who has been blind from
birth is like. One could try to describe
it, however Nagel argues that any attempt at describing the subjective
character of experience will be an abstraction from it, and will inevitably
make it lose it experiential nature.
That is why for instance Nagel claims reduction makes more sense with
something like water than for something like experience; we do not lose
anything fundamentally objective when we reduce water, however, with consciousness,
we do in fact lose a key feature of it upon abstraction.
While
Nagel does doubt that one will ever transcend the limitations of external
analysis of the subjective experience of consciousness, he proposes that
science should adopt a phenomenological enterprise as a means to perhaps
understand the a priori structures of
the mind as an effort to construct the experience of something externally. For instance, on page 439, Nagel describes
how he restricted to the resources of his own mind when trying to understand
the subjective experience of a bat. More
specifically, Nagel states ‘I cannot perform it either by imagining additions
to my present experience, or by imagining segments gradually subtracted from
it, or by imagining some combination of additions, subtraction and
modifications’ (pg. 439). So within the
limited scope of the imagination, an understanding of the structure of
experience seems impossible, and that is why it is desirable, and even
necessary to develop an empirical and scientific basis for understanding
experience. If science can find ground
the structure of experience empirically, perhaps one could create a working
representation of the fundamental ‘what it is like to be’. Perhaps one will reach this science of
experience by virtue of the addition, subtraction and modification Nagel
describes; if it is discovered that certain structures presuppose a certain
kind of experience, then it seems that one could create representation of an
experience through a manipulation of those structures. This may be a potential solution to the
subjective and objective problem as Nagel poses it.
In
summation, Nagel’s article casts doubt on the application of the reductionist
method to consciousness. Because consciousness
remains a mystery and it participates in the category of mind, the mind is also
a mystery, making any attempt at reduction of the mind vacuous. In order to ever gain an understanding of the
mind, one must gain an understanding of the ‘phenomenological features’ of
consciousness, which are only available to those who possess said
consciousness. The only way out of the
mind/body problem, or even the mind/consciousness problem, is perhaps the
phenomenological science Nagel proposes.
Work
Cited:
Nagel,
Thomas. ‘What is it like to be a Bat?’. The
Philosophical Review, Vol. 83, No.4 (Oct., 1974). Pp. 435-450.
No comments:
Post a Comment