Friday, 27 July 2012

Philosophy, Fear and Man’s Quest for Meaning


Philosophy, Fear and Man’s Quest for Meaning
To assume that philosophy is carried out purely objectively in an arena void of fear is to be ignorant of the extent to which this basic human disposition undermines one’s philosophical authenticity.  Practicing philosophy can lead to the examination of metaphysical views that can strike fear in the heart of many.  This fear leads to conflicts with philosophy’s search for truths of the world, for if the search for truth leads to something disheartening one may create one’s own idea of the way the world functions to avoid it.  However other philosophers have chosen not to flee from this threat and instead affirm the harsh reality of the world.  What does fear take from philosophers?  Nothing, if we grant that the final word in the matter to be the individual’s response to fear, namely his/her choice between the seemingly natural/ontic instinct of; ‘fight or flight’.  Therefore, fear shouldn’t be seen as an entity that controls us; it instead gives rise to the contingency of the universe, giving us a choice between affirming truths of the world and denying them.  In this essay I will argue that, in relation to the question of a meaningful existence, some proponents of existentialism, namely Friedrich Nietzsche, Jean-Paul Sartre and Albert Camus, can be seen as embodying the principle of fight (affirmation), while past philosophers like Renee Descartes and Plato, instead succumb to the need of a flight from reality (denial).
            When faced with a direct threat from the external world, one will either face the threat or flee.  There is a sense in which this dichotomy also permeates down to our day-to-day choices.  For instance, when fearing the possibility that a significant other is being unfaithful, one can either take the grounds for doubting the integrity of the relationship seriously and confront the other or instead reject the possibility and act as if the relationship remains untouched.  If there are are in fact good reasons for doubting the integrity of the relationship, it is clear that one may not want to confront the truth of a relationship in shambles and will instead lie to oneself as a means of escaping the truth. It can be said that everyone wants truth concerning themselves and the world to a certain degree, although it is clear that some are more willing to fabricate their own ideas about reality, in the sense of Sartre’s mauvaise foi, instead of facing a crude reality.  Is it fair to demand this affirmation of reality from everyone?  Absolutely not, for he who kneels at the feet of reality and affirms its objectivity regardless of one’s own needs and desires for what it must be should be seen as the exception and not the rule.  However, is it fair to demand this from philosophers?  There is a sense in which being a philosopher is nothing more than the rigorous application of this principle to one’s life.
            Does service to truth require sacrifice?  Absolutely, affirming truth requires that one negate the comfortable layers of assumptions which one has of the world and the self.  However, negating sentimental notions of self and world can be devastating for those caught up in what Heidegger would coin as a ‘pre-ontological’ framework. The assumptions that serve as the basis of this framework tend to be intuitive and socially constructed, yet fail to function as effective foundational axioms in the Cartesian sense.  If one exercises a dedicated will-to-truth, one grows weary of the fanciful assumptions that guided one’s life in an unreflective past.  As Nietzsche says, "No suffering has ever been able, nor will be able, to tempt me to bear false witness to life."[1]  In terms of metaphysical assumptions Nietzsche is saying that it may be comforting to assume the existence of a purpose to life, a logos or even a transcendent realm, as these beliefs provide one with an illusory understanding in the context of death, the unknown, yet the level of which answers are ‘comforting’ or ‘practical’ has no bearing on the philosophical value of any of these propositions. 
            The ‘dualist’ notion of the self for instance also has its roots in the inability to overcome fear, for why else would Descartes have seen, in a world seemingly mechanistic in nature, the existence of a substance (or exception) free of spatial-temporal limitations, capable of immortality, other than for the practical reason that it would serve the socially therapeutic function of giving life meaning?  While I do not wish to discard Descartes’s claim solely on the grounds that it provided him and others a solace, as doing so would be committing the genetic fallacy, I merely wish to submit that Descartes’s claim is based on an intuitive and religiously influenced conception of man and the universe.  Notions like these are infectious; they tend to our fear of death by giving us the illusion of mortality and sentience, yet bring us nowhere closer to truth.  John Searle has argued that the solution to the mind/body problem is simply that ‘all of our mental phenomena are caused by lower level neuronal processes in the brain and are themselves realized in the brain as higher level, or system, features.”[2]  In fact, the notion of ‘substance-dualism’ is incoherent and tends to give rise to non-problems in philosophy.  For instance, the question of ‘how is it that the body, a material substance, and the mind, an immaterial substance, co-relate?’ is intrinsically meaningless. It is not surprising that Descartes chose to flee from applying the counter-intuitive mechanistic conception of the universe to everything within it; the seemingly appropriate thing to do as society would have been faced with so ghastly a truth concerning the nature of man. Philosophy in the time of Descartes did serve a social/religious function: as Franz Rosenzweig, in the opening passage of The Star of Redemption, observes, “Philosophy takes it upon itself to throw off the fear of things earthly, to rob death of its poisonous sting, and Hades of its pestilential breath.”[3] 
            But what of a world comprised of the earthly, the mortal and the contingent?  Does this notion of reality not lead to a void of meaning?  As Soren Kierkegaard proclaims, “If there were no eternal consciousness in a man, if at the bottom of everything there were only a wild ferment, a power that twisting in dark passions produced everything great or inconsequential; if an unfathomable, insatiable emptiness lay hid beneath everything, what would life be but despair?”[4]  Kierkegaard’s illustration of a world without meaning may be rejected by some who choose not to believe it on the grounds that it paints a notion of the world too scary and bleak to be true.  Others however choose to affirm this model of the universe even if it comes at the cost of a sense of meaning in the world.  Sartre’s notion of nausée is essentially the emotional reaction one has to affirming the world as meaningless; it torments us at the base of our very existence.  There’s a sense in which the metaphysical truth purported by an absurd universe, stripped of the dogmas of God and immortality, is precisely what Nietzsche means in terms of an existential authenticity.  To assume the existentially authentic life, one must confront truth regardless of how scary it is; “How much truth can the mind bear, how much truth can the mind dare?  This is what gives me the veritable measure of value”[5] In this context Nietzsche can be seen as anticipating Albert Camus’s notion of the ‘absurd hero’; a being who affirms the absurdity of the cosmos and his own existence while not fleeing in terror, but instead shaping his life in the spirit of championing his disdain for such a universe. 
            The notion of an ‘absurd hero’ is crucial in understanding the ‘fight’ aspect of existentialism.  Existentialism, at least in the spirit of Nietzsche, is critical of past philosophers’ attempts at shying away from the world by euphemizing into categories, axioms and truths of reason what Nietzsche labels as ‘hocus-pocus’[6] and ignoring the significance of existing itself.  In ‘Beyond Good and Evil’, Nietzsche scoffs at the possibility of such ‘dogmatic’ methods as a  suitable means of deciphering truths about the world, “Speaking seriously, there are good reasons why all philosophical dogmatizing, however solemn and definitive its air used to be, may nevertheless have been no more than a noble childishness and tyronism.” (8) 
             In conclusion, at some point life every person is philosopher. Everyone must at one time analyse the aspects of life one holds of utmost importance.  However, one can never rid himself or herself entirely of the influence fear of death and meaninglessness have on his or her quest for meaning.  One can choose for instance, to flee from the absurd nature of the world and live in world of idealistic certainty or instead fight the absurdity as an absurd hero and place life itself as the meaning of life.  However, there will always be a sense in which fear will dictate all philosophical progress.  If one affirms that life is nothing but absurdity and lives in opposition to it, what is the sense of granting special status to an absurd hero?  If reality is nothing but a shadowy representation of a transcendent world, why then take the time to glorify the fallen world with truths of reason?  The truth is that all philosophers are uncertain about themselves and the world.  Fear of this uncertainty is what gives us the thirst for knowledge.

[1] Letter to Malwida von Meysenbug, from Naumburg, 14th January, 1880.
[2] J.Searle, "Why I am Not a Property Dualist”, p.1
 [3] F. Rosenzweig, “The Star of Redemption”, p.3
[4] S. Kierkegaard, “Fear and trembling, and the Sickness Unto Death”, p.14
[5] F. Nietzsche, “The Will to Power”, p.154
[6] F. Nietzsche, Human, all-too-human: parts 1 and 2 ; Beyond good and evil”, p.5




Work Cited
Kierkegaard, Søren. Fear and trembling, and The sickness unto death;. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1954. Print.
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. Letter to Malwida von Meysenbug, from Naumburg, 14th January, 1880.
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. Human, all too human: a book for free spirits. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1984. Print.
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm, and Walter Arnold Kaufmann. Thus spoke Zarathustra: a book for all and none. New York: Modern Library, 1995. Print.
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm, and Helen Zimmern. Human, all-too-human: parts 1 and 2 ; Beyond good and evil. London: Wordsworth Editions, 2008. Print.

Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm, Walter Arnold Kaufmann, and R. J. Hollingdale. The will to power . New York: Random House, 1967. Print. 

Rosenzweig, Franz. The Star of Redemption . [1st ed. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1971. Print.

Searle, John . "Why I am Not a Property Dualist." Consciousness Studies 12.9 (2002): 57-64. Print.

No comments:

Post a Comment